Ethical-fading-2004 - Ethical Fading: The Role of Self-Deception in Unethical Behavior PDF

Title Ethical-fading-2004 - Ethical Fading: The Role of Self-Deception in Unethical Behavior
Course Business Ethics and Leadership Development
Institution Wright State University
Pages 15
File Size 311 KB
File Type PDF
Total Downloads 24
Total Views 144

Summary

Ethical Fading: The Role of Self-Deception in Unethical Behavior...


Description

Social Justice Research, Vol. 17, No. 2, June 2004 (°C 2004)

Ethical Fading: The Role of Self-Deception in Unethical Behavior Ann E. Tenbrunsel1,3 and David M. Messick2

This paper examines the root of unethical dicisions by identifying the psychological forces that promote self-deception. Self-deception allows one to behave self-interestedly while, at the same time, falsely believing that one’s moral principles were upheld. The end result of this internal con game is that the ethical aspects of the decision “fade” into the background, the moral implications obscured. In this paper we identify four enablers of self-deception, including language euphemisms, the slippery slope of decision-making, errors in perceptual causation, and constraints induced by representations of the self. We argue that current solutions to unethical behaviors in organizations, such as ethics training, do not consider the important role of these enablers and hence will be constrained in their potential, producing only limited effectiveness. Amendments to these solutions, which do consider the powerful role of self-deception in unethical decisions, are offered. KEY WORDS: ethics; decision making; self-deception; ethics training.

“To see the self as deceiving itself has seemed the only way to explain what might otherwise be incomprehensible: a person’s failure to acknowledge what is too obvious to miss” (Bok, 1989, p. 60) While there has been a rush to explain and remedy the unethical corporate practices that now seem commonplace, one of the newest entrants—the psychological processes behind unethical decision making—appears to be the most promising. In 1966, Messick and Tenbrunsel argued for the integration of psychology 1 2 3

Mendoza College of Business, University of Notre Dame, Notre Dame, Indiana. Kellogg School of Management, Northwestern University, Evanston, Illinois. All correspondence should be addressed to Ann E. Tenbrunsel, Mendoza College of Business, University of Notre Dame, Notre Dame, Indiana 46556-0399; e-mail: [email protected]. 223 C 2004 Plenum Publishing Corporation 0885-7466/04/0600-0223/0 °

224

Tenbrunsel and Messick

and behavioral economics into the field of business ethics. Such integration, they assert, would allow for the normatively based questions of “ought” to be considered alongside the equally important questions of “how.” Dienhart et al. (2001) compiled a series of papers, entitled The Next Phase of Business Ethics: Integrating Psychology and Ethics, which illustrate the range of phenomena that define the intersection of these areas. We argue that the process of self-deception is at the root of this juncture of disciplines. Self-deception causes the moral implications of a decision to fade, allowing individuals to behave incomprehensibly and, at the same time, not realize that they are doing so. The promise of the psychological perspective is not reflected in the current solution of choice for unethical behavior, namely “ethics training.” Corporations and business schools have been urged to deliver such instruction and training with the hope that executives in turn will make more moral decisions. More than half of organizations provide training to their employees (Joseph, 2003). Business ethics programs have grown at a rapid rate in the best business schools in the country and in the latest ratings of business schools, the category of ethics is explicitly used as an evaluative dimension. While the intention is good, we wonder whether it will achieve the desired end product, namely a reduction in unethical behavior. Could scandals such as Enron, Worldcom, and Adelphia have been avoided if their executives had received more ethics training? We argue that the answer to this question is no. Ethics training has been argued to be short-lived (Richards, 1999) and codes of conduct, usually part of the educational process, have in some cases produced no discernible difference in behavior (Badaracco and Webb, 1995). According to a recent survey, more than half of the MBA graduates did not feel that the ethics training they received in business schools was very useful in addressing the ethical issues they face in the workplace (Business Week Online, 2003). We argue that one of the reasons for such potential ineffectiveness is the narrow focus of such training. Typical instruction includes an overview of ethical theory, discussion of ethical principles, and applications of such principles using a case-based method. Such instruction assumes that by highlighting and emphasizing the moral components of decisions, executives will be more likely to choose the moral path. Missing from this paradigm, however, is the failure to acknowledge the innate psychological tendency for individuals to engage in self-deception. Individuals do not “see” the moral components of an ethical decision, not so much because they are morally uneducated, but because psychological processes fade the “ethics” from an ethical dilemma. We introduce the term “ethical fading” to define the process by which the moral colors of an ethical decision fade into bleached hues that are void of moral implications. If we are correct, educating individuals on moral principles is only useful when individuals perceive that the decision has ethical coloration, but useless when ethical fading has occurred or may occur.

Ethical Fading: The Role of Self-Deception in Unethical Behavior

225

Efforts to improve ethical decision making, then, may be better directed toward understanding these psychological tendencies. The purpose of this paper is to provide a framework in which to enhance this understanding. . We then identify and describe four reasons why such deception is perpetuated, including the role of language euphemisms, the slippery slope of decision making, errors in perceptual causation, and constraints induced by representations of the self. We link this discussion to the concept of decision frames, which we argue act as catalysts for ethical fading. We argue that self-deception and decision frames are part of the sequence linking environmental cues to unethical behavior, with environmental cues acting as prompts for selfdeception, which in turn decreases the likelihood that an ethical frame is adopted, thus increasing unethical behavior. We conclude with implications for increasing ethical behavior in organizations.

THE ART OF SELF-DECEPTION Self-deception is defined as being unaware of the processes that lead us to form our opinions and judgments (Messick and Bazerman, 1996). Such deception involves avoidance of the truth, the lies that we tell to, and the secrets we keep from, ourselves (Bok, 1989). This practice is common, normal, and accepted as constant and pervasive in individuals’ lives. . We believe our stories and thus believe that we are objective about ourselves. We argue that self-deception is instrumental in the process of ethical fading. An ethical decision often involves a tradeoff between self-interest and moral principles. Ignorance and false beliefs about oneself can create errors in judgments concerning moral responsibility and in estimates of the amount of harm that is caused, as well as obscure means to reverse an immoral decision (Bok, 1989). Self-deceit is thus seen as standing in the way of morality. Indeed, it has been asserted that if individuals could rid themselves of such self-deceit, then they would be more capable of making moral decisions and leading nobler lives (Bok, 1989). The importance of self-deception in unethical decision making is clear, despite the fact that it is unclear whether such deception is the result of a conscious act or an unconscious process. Self-deception is paradoxical in this sense, for to deceive oneself somehow implies that one must know that something needs to be hidden or kept secret (Bok, 1989, p. 61). Psychoanalysis has offered the concept of the

226

Tenbrunsel and Messick

split-selves as one mechanism that may help explain this paradox (Demos, 1960; Fingarette, 1969; Freud, 1957; Haight, 1980). The question of whether it is a process of which we are aware or one which exists below the surface, however, remains a debated point. What is evident is that we need to acknowledge the pervasiveness of selfdeception and its role in unethical decision making. As Messick and Bazerman (1996) state, “if we can accept the fact that the human mind has an infinite, creative capacity to trick itself, we can guard against irrational, unethical decisions.” Understanding the mechanisms by which self-deception is exacerbated, the “enablers” if you will, becomes the necessary next step. In the following discussion, we identify four such enablers: language euphemisms, the slippery slope of decision making, biased perceptual causation, and the constrained representation of our self.

Language Euphemisms Language euphemisms are the “disguised” stories we tell ourselves about our unethical actions. These stories are an edited version of the “real” story, devoid of all ethical implications. Through renaming actions we take and relabeling decisions we make, we turn what may be unacceptable into socially approved behaviors. Euphemistic language can make harmful conduct respectable and, as such, is an “injurious” weapon (Bandura, 1999).

Some of these illustrate the tendency to replace morally repugnant language with more abstract and neutral terms. In other cases the goal is to connote something more or less benign, depending on what is in our best self-interest. So in the Middle East, the barrier that is being erected by Israel is referred to as a “fence” by the Israelis and as a “wall” by the Palestinians. A wall connotes that those inside are in a sort of “ghetto” which would be repugnant to the Israelis, and a “fence” connotes neighborliness, which the Palestinians see as completely misleading. The fact is that it is very easy to find the words to color a story in such a way that it becomes appealing to the narrator and consistent with the narrator’s morality. The accounting term “pro forma” falls into this same category. Until recently, companies used to report earnings on a pro-forma basis, which acted “as if” certain ordinary expenses did not really exist. The use of this term enabled corporate executives to make companies look better than they really were while in actuality, these “make your own accounting rules” facilitated deceptive and misleading presentations (Weil, 2003).

Ethical Fading: The Role of Self-Deception in Unethical Behavior

227

Messick (1999a) provides a vivid illustration of language euphemisms in the tobacco industry. To fight the growing body of research that indicated that tobacco was addictive, the industry fought to redefine the concept of addiction. While medical definitions of addition include multiple indications—including increased tolerance of a drug, withdrawal issues, brain mechanisms, and intoxicating qualities—the tobacco industry focused only on the intoxication criteria to conclude that smoking cigarettes was not addictive. The industry also re-labeled the debate from health to civil rights using terms such as “accommodation” (a term used to describe the process by which smokers and nonsmokers could coexist without government intervention); in doing so, they attempted to refocus attention away from risky health issues and toward civil rights issues, where the tobacco manufacturers stood on firmer ground. Using these and other strategies, the tobacco industry perfected “the strategy of blowing smoke at the claims” (Messick, 1999a, p. 82). Business schools have likewise been blamed for the creation of euphemisms that help to disguise unethical actions. Business schools have been accused of using “cold language,” which affects the way business students think (Browning, 2003). Terms such as “transaction costs, profit maximization, and rationalization” are argued to be devoid of the human and potential ethical dimensions of decisions. A case in point is the term “right sizing”—the favored terms for layoffs—which focuses attention toward the economic benefits and away from the human costs of putting people out of work. Albert Speer, a member of Hitler’s government and his innermost circle of advisors, provides another compelling example of the role of language euphemisms and their connection to self-deception (Speer, 1970). Speer played an integral part in the design of the munitions factories and was certainly knowledgeable of the treatment of the prisoner employees. However, by relabeling himself as an “architect” or “administrator,” he admits that he was able to convince himself that worrying about political, and in the end, human issues, was not his job. Social scientists have also uncovered the powerful role of language in the decision-making process. In a study of cooperation rates in ultimatum versus prisoner dilemma games, Larrick and Blount (1997) demonstrated that the differences in cooperation rates between social dilemmas and ultimatum bargaining games could be explained by the words used to describe these games. When faced with choices of “accepting” or “rejecting” offers, individuals were less likely to cooperate than when the choice was described as “claiming” part of a shared resource, even though outcomes were identical. Similarly, Pillutla and Chen (1999) found that when a social dilemma was described using economic language there was less cooperation than when the same dilemma (in payoff terms) was described using noneconomic words. Language euphemisms themselves are not dangerous. We need metaphors to help us simplify the complexity of our world. What is dangerous is when these

228

Tenbrunsel and Messick

metaphors hide the moral or ethical implications of our decisions. Metaphors such as “pro forma,” “creative accounting,” and “right sizing” can be so commonplace that we no longer see the questionable behavior that they were designed to disguise. Perhaps worse, the metaphors can be dangerously transformed from descriptions to explanations. In doing so, unethical behavior becomes justifiable through a process of deception, in which we transform morally wrong behavior into socially acceptable actions. When this occurs, we avoid the complexity inherent in ethical dilemmas and short-circuit our decision-making processes (Bok, 1989). The ethical pigments of our action have faded. The Slippery Slope of Decision Making The so-called “slippery slope” of decision making, the second enabler of selfdeception, consists of at least two separate psychological mechanisms. The first of these is a psychological numbing that comes from repetition. This process is aptly described by Bok (1989, p. 69) in her influential book on concealment: A related form of rejecting knowledge is what is known as “psychic numbing.” It comes much closer to what is often called self-deception, yet it can be a reflex response to overwhelming pain or fear. Recall an intensely painful experience, and notice that it is impossible to recapture the sheer physical sense of that pain. In the same way, the initial impact of suffering may wear off with repeated exposure, leaving us incapable of responding to what at first aroused sharp reactions.

In this sense, repeated exposures to ethical dilemmas may produce a form of ethical numbing in which self-reproof is diminished through repeated exposures (Bandura, 1999). When this occurs, we may be less likely to see the “ethical” in the dilemma, and hence engage in more unreflective and potentially more unethical behavior. The second component of the slippery slope problem is what we call the “induction” mechanism. Induction in mathematics is as follows. If a statement is true for N = 1, and if the statement for N + 1 is true assuming the truth of N, then the statement is true for all N. The way this works in organizations is similar. If what we were doing in the past is OK and our current practice is almost identical, then it too must be OK. This mechanism uses the past practices of an organization as a benchmark for evaluating new practices. If the past practices were ethical and acceptable, then practices that are similar and not too different are also acceptable. If each step away from ethical and acceptable practices is sufficiently small, small enough not to appear qualitatively different, then a series of these small steps can lead to a journey of unethical and illegal activities. This process of induction is very much like the process of routinization described by Kelman and Hamilton (1989). Routinization means that when a practice has become routine, it is ordinary, mundane, and acceptable. Any ethical coloration is lost. An excellent illustration of this process is offered by Maremont (1996) with the criminal prosecution of Bernard Bradstreet, Co-CEO of Kurzweil Applied

Ethical Fading: The Role of Self-Deception in Unethical Behavior

229

Intelligence, Inc., a manufacturer of high-tech voice recognition computers. Bradstreet was described by friends as a “straight arrow,” a man of impeccable moral stature. But in an effort to make the kind of financial record for Kurzweil that would allow the company to go public, Bradstreet, according to sources sited by Maremont, allowed sales reps to post sales that were not actually signed a few days in advance to meet financial targets. The goods would be shipped to a warehouse while the final terms of the deal were worked out. These few innocuous days stretched into weeks and as this happened, the certainty that the sale would be made also dropped. Eventually, some salesmen were forging customers’ signatures on contracts (believing that the sales would eventually happen). When auditors came to examine the books and wrote to the alleged customers, bogus responses “confirming” the sales were also forged. Thus a completely false impression of Kurzweil’s financial health was created through deception and fraud. At trial, Mr Bradstreet defended his actions as appropriate. The story of Mr. Bradstreet and Kurzweil is but one of many that could be told to illustrate the dangerous consequences of the slippery slope. It follows the old adage that “one lie perpetuates many more.” Part of this is due to our inability to see the incremental steps we take down the road of unethical behavior, due to the self-deception that occurs along the way. Errors in Perceptual Causation What our language and baby steps cannot filter out, our errors in why things occur can. Causation is complex and humans are self-interested and fallible. The end result: misconstrued judgments about moral responsibility. There are three reasons why individual perceptions of causes can go awry—a focus on individuals rather than systems, self-interested motives in the assignment of blame, and a blurred moral responsibility involving acts of omission (Messick and Bazerman, 1996). First, individuals tend to focus on a person rather than a system in assessing and remedying problematic situations. Individual fallibilities are often more apparent than the complex errors that mark technology and systems. Because of our assumption that systems are “error proof,” we overlook environmental causes of unethical behavior, in turn reducing the probability that the system will be improved. Tenbrunsel and Messick (1999) found for example, that the presence of a monitoring system designed to decrease undesirable behavior actually produced an increase. The tendency to look at human causes might lead one to conclude that employees are to be trusted even less, further focusing attention on improving the monitoring system. Their results, however, suggest that it may be the system that is the real culprit. Our proclivity to focus only on the person may thus lead us to overlook other, more likely causes, which reduces the likelihood that the frequency of unethical behavior will be diminished.

230

Tenbrunsel and Messick

Causal explanations are also in danger of inaccuracy because of the selfinterested motives that may influence assignment of blame. In an investigation of perceived caus...


Similar Free PDFs